|
Viewpoint Stem cells stir controversy
By MARK WAYMACK
Embryonic stem cells are on the
cutting edge of todays human tissue engineering, yet they are
controversial. An ongoing debate over federal funding for research in this
field has highlighted the ethical problems involved. There are a lot of
Sophies Choices in this, said Alan Russell, a molecular
biologist who heads the University of Pittsburghs chemical engineering
department.
Many abortion foes, contending that un-implanted embryos are every
bit as human as a fetus, have opposed funding. President Bush has expressed his
personal opposition to this type of research and has asked Health and Human
Services Secretary Tommy Thompson -- an abortion foe but, as Wisconsin
governor, a supporter of embryonic stem-cell research -- to review federal
guidelines. Biotechnology experts worry that without such research, U.S.
biotech companies might fall behind those in other countries, notably Britain,
that allow embryonic stem-cell experiments.
Medical researchers now argue that these cells hold the promise
for highly effective treatments for many diseases that afflict us. The list of
medical conditions that their use might help includes diabetes,
Parkinsons and Alzheimers diseases, perhaps leukemia, even spinal
cord injuries. Many researchers, physicians, patients and politicians are
clamoring for greater support for such research. But there are others, as well,
who argue that such practices should not be supported since they are the
equivalent of murder. How have we become so divided?
Embryonic stem cells are, without a doubt, remarkable. After the
ovum is fertilized it begins to divide. One cell becomes two, then four, then
eight, 16, and so on. At these early stages, each cell is virtually identical
to the others. But by the time the fetus emerges into our world, he or she has
changed dramatically. From that small, one cell start, he or she has emerged as
a being of millions of cells, and those cells are specialized in their
structure and function. Brain cells are different from liver cells, which are
different from skin cells, which are different from muscle cells, and so on.
And putting muscle cells into a brain will not change them into new brain
cells. Those cells in the early embryo, what we call the embryonic stem cells,
are special in that they carry the capacity to become all the different kinds
of cells in the body.
Researchers can take those embryonic stem cells and culture large
quantities of them. What they hope to learn to do well is to then transplant
those stem cells into an individuals diseased organ -- the pancreas, the
lungs, the liver, the bone marrow, the brain -- and have the healthy stem cells
proliferate, specialize into the needed function and thus take over the role of
the diseased cells.
Clinical trials thus far have not been very successful; but there
is reason to believe that with diligent work the technique will become more
effective.
Some researchers want to push ahead for the fame of success or for
financial profit. Many who lobby for advancing research argue on the grounds of
moral obligation. Do we not have an obligation to give succor? To aid those in
need? Did not Christ heal and admonish us to heal? Most of us accept a
responsibility to care for others, including those in medical need.
Traditionally religious organizations have been active in providing health
care, seeing it as a moral obligation. If then, we see a promising avenue of
medical research, an avenue that could possibly provide comfort, relief and
even cure for perhaps millions of people, do we not have a moral obligation to
pursue it?
For many, the issue is not that straightforward. The problems
revolve around the moral status of the embryo and, consequently, our
obligations to the embryo.
If one sees the embryo as simply a collection of undifferentiated
cells, then there would be no moral problem with using these stem cells for our
own benefit. Consider, for example, how skin is routinely cultured into large
sheets to be used for skin grafts for severely burned patients. Few of us think
of those skin cells, growing into living, pliable sheets of skin, as having any
special moral status. The burn surgeon trims the edges of the graft to fit the
wound and throws away the trimmings, and no one gives those cells a second
thought. It seems difficult to deny that relieving widespread suffering
is morally better than destroying embryos at no gain, says Louis Guenin
of Harvard Medical School, who also argues that up to day 14, a fertilized egg
can become twins, so no human identity exists before this time.
But many think differently. Under the right circumstances, that
small collection of undifferentiated cells has the possibility to be born as a
unique human being. For some, this means that the embryo deserves special
respect. It does not necessarily mean that the embryo has a full-fledged right
to life. For being special need not mean the same thing as being a bearer of
full moral rights. For these thinkers, we should be respectful toward the
embryos we use. We should not use them casually. But, given that the primary
source for embryonic stem cells is the frozen leftovers from in vitro
fertilization, leftovers that will be destroyed anyway, why not allow something
good to come from them? From this point of view, embryonic stem cell research
and use may require guidelines and oversight, but the compelling obligation to
help those individuals who are sick, and who are fully fledged bearers of moral
rights and objects of our moral concern, can easily override respect for the
embryo.
However, if we think of the embryo as a person, as a human being
with a right to life, then harvesting embryonic stem cells would be a
deliberate killing of another human being. And that, of course, is morally
wrong. Well, it is usually morally wrong.
Even if we presume that the early embryo counts as an individual
with full moral standing, the answer may still be complicated. We have, as can
be seen, conflicting moral obligations. An obligation to help and an obligation
not to kill. An obligation to do good versus an obligation to do right, so to
speak. But which takes precedence?
Most of us do not take the injunction not to kill as an absolute.
We might allow the killing of an aggressor if that is the only way to defend
our own lives. We might find justification for killing the enemy in a morally
just war. In what way can an embryo in a petri dish be said to be an aggressor?
And if the embryo is not an aggressor, but an innocent bystander, there must be
very special circumstances to justify overriding the prohibition against
murder.
Finally, even if one regards the destruction of the embryo for our
own medical benefit as an immoral murder, one must still confront a different
consideration. Embryonic stem-cell research is already being conducted in the
United States. Private research money can be, and is being, spent in this
activity. It thus proceeds with little public oversight. An argument for
allowing federal money to be used would be as a strategy to gain federal
oversight and thus perhaps lessen some of the moral evils that might happen
otherwise.
Should we dirty our hands to try to prevent greater evil? Or
should we stand aside and uphold our moral rectitude even though that might
lead to more harm to embryos than otherwise? The debate, then, revolves around
two key issues: 1) the moral status of the embryo, and 2) the conflicting moral
obligations to help others (to do good) versus the moral obligation not to
murder (to do right). We will need patience, attentiveness and wisdom as we
seek a consensus.
Mark Waymack is associate professor of philosophy and
co-director of graduate programs in health care ethics at Loyola University
Chicago.
National Catholic Reporter, July 27,
2001
|
|